From: PSYCOLOQUY (Electronic Journal) <psyc_coglit.soton.ac.uk> Date: Fri, 14 Aug 1998 12:01:26 +0100 (BST) To: psyc_coglit.psy.soton.ac.uk Subject: Psycoloquy disposition: Harpaz. Cc: yeh_harlequin.co.uk Dear Yehouda Harpaz, Enclosed are the five referee reports on your manuscript: "The Neurons in the Brain Cannot Implement Symbolic Systems". Unfortunately, these reports do not give me a basis for accepting your article for publication in Psycoloquy, nor for recommending revision and resubmission. Although there are arguments and evidence in the literature to the effect that the brain is not doing only symbol processing, there is no reason to suppose that symbol processing cannot be implemented by neurons. Thank you for allowing Psycoloquy to consider your manuscript. Sincerely, Stevan Harnad -------------------------------------------------------------------- Stevan Harnad harnad_cogsci.soton.ac.uk Professor of Psychology harnad_princeton.edu Director, phone: +44 1703 592582 Cognitive Sciences Centre fax: +44 1703 594597 Department of Psychology http://www.cogsci.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/ University of Southampton http://www.princeton.edu/~harnad/ Highfield, Southampton ftp://ftp.princeton.edu/pub/harnad/ SO17 1BJ UNITED KINGDOM ftp://cogsci.soton.ac.uk/pub/harnad/ -------------------------------------------------------------------- REFEREE #1 Anonymous Ordinarily I would like very much to referee papers for you. In this case, the claim seems so patently self-contradictory that it would be a waste of time. What does the author think he is doing, if not symbolic processing? And what does he do it with, if not neurons? What is Broca's area for, if not symbolic processes ? Etc. -------------------------------------------------------------------- REFEREE #2 Anonymous I'd say it's nonsense -- just look at Minsky's book on Finite and Infinite Machines! -------------------------------------------------------------------- REFEREE #3 Anonymous I reviewed this paper for another journal and rejected it as having no substantial content. -------------------------------------------------------------------- REFEREE #4 Anonymous It's of no value. Moreover, I reviewed it in March for another publication; I thought it was of no value then, too. Here is a copy of the review I sent them. The author may have made some revisions since then; the section numbers I reference below don't seem to match this version. But the paper is not substantially different. The author purports to show that brains cannot implement symbol processing operations because they cannot copy tokens reliably. But he admits in the first paragraph of section 7 that people can in fact handle symbols. (And contrary to the claim made a few paragraphs later, such symbols are not necessarily tied directly to sensory inputs, since people are perfectly capable of manipulating sentences, formulas, diagrams, and concepts they dream up in their heads.) So the author tries to imply that just because people can handle symbols, this does not mean that BRAINS can handle symbols. Actually, he doesn't say something quite that ridiculous; he argues (p. 14) that "the components of the brain" cannot handle symbols. But this is an entirely different claim than the paper started out with and concludes with, i.e., that the brain as a whole is not a symbol processor. Since no one ever claimed that individual neurons or small groups of neurons were symbol processing systems, the author's central argument is revealed as an attack on a straw man. The paper concludes with a long series of silly statements, such as (p. 18) "handling language does not require any dynamic mechanism" because the meanings of words are static. (What about the need to dynamically construct representations of novel sentences?) And (p. 21) "Neuroscientists do not realize the importance of the stochasic connectivity for theories of cognition". Obviously, this is not a scholarly paper. And the central argument is nonsense. I recommend that the paper be rejected. -------------------------------------------------------------------- REFEREE #5 Anonymous This paper argues that the brain cannot represent symbolic systems. The conclusion appears to be obviously false, the literature review is shoddy, and the paper is not well-argued. Commentaries on this piece are unlilkely to substnatially advance our understanding. I therefore recommend against publication. Symbols in conscious deliberate thought & Dualism The reason that the argument appears to be doomed from the outset is that the human brain appears to at least be able to simulate symbolic systems in conscious, deliberate thought. Thus even those radical connectionists who would deny that symbol-manipulation plays much role in some areas of cognition make an exception for "serial, deliberate reasoning" or "conscious rule application". For example, Touretzky & Hinton (1988) wrote that "many phenomena which appear to requires explicit rules can be handled by using connection strengths [but...] we do not believe that this removes the need for a more explicit representation of rules in tasks that more closely resemble serial, deliberate reasoning. A person can be told an explicit rule such as "i before e except after c" and can then apply this rule to the relevant cases." If the brain can manipulate symbols there, any argument with the conclusion that the brain cannot manipulate (or represent) symbols must be mistaken. The author addresses this point briefly in paragraphs 47-50, but the response given there seems incoherent. If the brain a whole can represent symbols, then the brain can represent symbols. The author seems to be resorting to a kind of dualism in which a person can manipulate symbols, but a brain cannot. Everything we know about cognitive neuroscience and cognitive neuorpsychology makes this sort of dualism untenable. Where has the author gone wrong? As I reconstruct his argument the premises are as follows. 1. the processing in the brain is done by neurons. 2, every mechanism in the brain must be implemented by neurons. 3. neurons are stochastic. 4. stochastic neurons cannot implement symbols Therefore 5. The brain cannot implement symbols. Which premise is wrong? Premise 1 is likely right, but not entirely beyond doubt; the same goes for Premise 2. Premise 3 may be correct for some neurons and not for others. Here, the author to some extent confuses gaps in our collective knowledge of neuroscience with limitations on what is possible. One might have formed a similar argument in Mendel's time to argue against the possibility of their being genes. The main problem is with Premise 4, a premise that rests more on a poverty of imagination than on any in-principle argument. Note that there is at least some stochasticity in a standard computer, albeit of a different sort (e.g., radiation emitted from a sunspot might affect the memory register that contains the thirty-seventh character in this symbolically stored e-mail message). If we accept the fact that sunspots introduce some stochasticity into computers, the form of argument expressed in 4 would lead to the false conclusion that computers are not symbolic. (The author seems to think that these two kinds of stochasticity differ in an important way relevant to the argument, but I am unable to follow the author's argument.) Other general comments The manuscript is unclear. Having read through this manuscript several times, I still don't fully understand the author's argument. (Some examples are listed below.) The literature review is shoddy, which is especially worrisome since the author frequently takes gaps in the literature to be indicative of in principle arguments; often such gaps only reflect the authors's unfamiliarity with the literature. (See various references below.) Other comments. Paragraph 7 is confusing. Isn't the storage of a symbol a kind of computation? Also, the requirement of arbitrariness seems unmotivated. It's also not clear that symbols *must* be stored; one could build a symbolic computer a la McCulloch & Pitts (1943) that passed along symbolic activation values without storing them. Paragraph 13: There may be mechanisms of short-term synaptic plasticity that have not yet been identified. See Gallistel (1994) for an argument that such mechansism must exist, even if they have not yet been identified. Also, see Gallistel (1998, in the 4th volume of the Osherson MIP Ress COgntive Science Introduction.) Why can there be no way in which "distal events can affect the strength of specific synapse"? Paragraph 15: Maybe the selection of these neurons is systematatic, but in ways that neuroscientists have not yet come to understand. Paragraph 23. Point about cell populations is important, but should not have been ignored in Section VI. Paragraph 24 confuses "specialized" with "prespecified"; targets of given vertrbrate neurons may not be prespecified but may still be specialized. (See, e.g., Rakic, 1995). Paragraph 24 Constructions like "worst example" (other examples may be foudn throughout) are unduly condescending. Paragraph 43. I don't undertsnad the argument and/or the evidence here. Paragraph 52, 56. Re: behavioral tests and insights from symbols: The work of Pinker on connectionism is very relevant here. (See (Marcus, Brinkmann, Clahsen, Wiese, & Pinker, 1995; Pinker, 1991; Pinker & Prince, 1988) Likewise, Fodor & Pylyshyn (1988) have argued that symbols give the only account of compositionality. Paragraph 53: No argument is given to show that the symbolic approach does not work. Also, what would the author take as evidence for the symbolic approach? Paragraph 54: Even if symbols had not yet yielded insight in to neurobiology, that would not mean that they couldn't. Again, Mendel's postulate of genes took a number of years before it lead to direct understand of molecular mechanisms. References Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition. 28, 3-71. Gallistel, C.R. (1994). Foraging for brain stimulation: toward a neurobiology of computation. Cognition, 50, 151-170. Marcus, G. F., Brinkmann, U., Clahsen, H., Wiese, R., & Pinker, S. (1995). German inflection: The exception that proves the rule. Cognitive Psychology. 29, 186-256. McCulloch, W. S., & Pitts, W. (1943). A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. Bulletin of mathematical biophysics. 5, 115-133. Pinker, S. (1991). Rules of Language. Science. 253, 530-55. Pinker, S., & Prince, A. (1988). On language and connectionism: Analysis of a Parallel Distributed Processing model of language acquisition. Cognition. 28, 73-193. Rakic, P. (1995). Corticigenesis in Human and Nonhuman Primates. In M.S. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The Cognitive Neurosciences (pp. 127-145). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Touretzky, D.S., & Hinton, G.E. (1988). A distributed connectionist production system. Cognitive Science, 12, 423-466. --------------------------------------------------------------------